An introduction to Lie algebra cohomology/lecture 8b
reference
We follow Humphreys, 1972 closely for those parts that are not explicitly concerned with cohomology.
the field
Although we use \(\mathbb{C}\) as our field, one can also do the initial part of this section with an arbitrary field.
At some point we will need the field to have characteristic zero, and a bit later we want it to be closed.
The latter condition can be slightly relaxed, but we need to find the roots of the characteristic equation of the ad-action of elements in the Lie algebra.
the Casimir operator
definition - dual basis
Let \(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}=\mathfrak{g}/\ker d_1\) (This makes sense, since \(\ker d_1\) is an ideal).
A trace form \( K_\mathfrak{a}\) on \(\mathfrak{g}\) induces a trace form \(\tilde{K}_\mathfrak{a}\) on \(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}\) by \[\tilde{K}_\mathfrak{a}([x],[y])=K_\mathfrak{a}(x,y)\] Suppose \(\dim_\mathbb{C}\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}=n<\infty\ .\) Let \( e_1,\cdots,e_n\) be a basis of \(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}\ .\)
If \(\tilde{K}_\mathfrak{a}\) is nondegenerate, then define \(e^1,\cdots,e^n\) to be the dual basis with respect to \(\tilde{K}_\mathfrak{a}\ ,\) that is, \(\tilde{K}_\mathfrak{a}(e_i,e^j)=\delta_i^j\ .\)
example
Let, for \(\mathfrak{g}=\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}=\mathfrak{sl}_2\ ,\) the basis be given by \[e_1=M,\quad e_2=N,\quad e_3=H\] Then a dual basis is given by \[ e^1=N,\quad e^2=M,\quad e^3=\frac{1}{2} H\]
proposition
Suppose \( [e_i,e_j]=\sum_{k=1}^n c_{ij}^k e_k\ .\) Then \([e^i,e_j]=\sum_{k=1}^n c_{jk}^i e^k\ .\)
proof
The structure constants \(c_{ij}^k\) can be expressed in terms of the trace form as follows. \[ \tilde{K}_\mathfrak{a}([e_i,e_j],e^k)=\sum_{s=1}^n c_{ij}^s \tilde{K}_\mathfrak{a}(e_s,e^k)=\sum_{s=1}^n c_{ij}^s \delta_s^k=c_{ij}^k\] Let \([e^i,e_j]=\sum_{k=1}^n d_{jk}^i e^k\ .\) Then \[\tilde{K}_\mathfrak{a}(e_k,[e^i,e_j])=\sum_{s=1}^n d_{js}^i \tilde{K}_\mathfrak{a}(e_k,e^s)=\sum_{s=1}^n d_{js}^i \delta_k^s=d_{jk}^i\] The result follows from the \(\mathfrak{g}\)-invariance of \(\tilde{K}_\mathfrak{a}\ :\) \[\tilde{K}_\mathfrak{a}(e_k,[e^i,e_j])=-\tilde{K}_\mathfrak{a}(e_k,[e_j,e^i])=\tilde{K}_\mathfrak{a}([e_j,e_k],e^i)=c_{jk}^i\]
corollary
\[ [x,e^i]=-\sum_{k=1}^n \tilde{K}_\mathfrak{a}(x,[e_k,e^i])e^k\] and \( [x,e_i]=\sum_{k=1}^n \tilde{K}_\mathfrak{a}(x,[e_i,e^k])e_k\)
definition - Casimir
Define the Casimir operator \(\gamma\) by \[\gamma=\sum_{i=1}^n d_1(e^i)d_1(e_i) \in End(\mathfrak{a})\]
remark
For the Casimir to exist one only needs finite-dimensionality of \(\mathfrak{g}\ ,\) \(\mathfrak{a}\) can be infinite dimensional.
Only when \(K_{\mathfrak{a}}\) plays a role, one assumes \(\mathfrak{a}\) to be finite-dimensional, just so that one does not have to worry about traces in infinite-dimensional spaces.
well defined
The \(e_i, e^i\) stand for equivalence classes, but taking different representatives does not change the value of \(\gamma\ .\)
The definition of \(\gamma\) is also independent of the choice of basis.
Let \( f_i=\sum_{k=1}^n A_i^k e_k\ ,\) with \(A\) an invertible matrix, be another basis, with dual basis \(f^i\ .\)
Let \(f^i=\sum_{k=1}^n B_k^i e^k\ .\)
Then \[\delta_j^i=K_\mathfrak{b}(e^i,e_j)=\sum_{k,l=1}^n B_k^i A_j^l K_\mathfrak{b}(f^k,f_l)=\sum_{k,l=1}^n B_k^i A_j^l\delta_l^k=\sum_{k=1}^n B_k^i A_j^k\] This shows that \[\gamma=\sum_{i=1}^n d_1(f^i)d_1(f_i)\]
corollary
If the dual basis is chosen with respect to \(K_\mathfrak{a}\ ,\) then \[ \mathrm{tr }(\gamma)=\sum_{i=1}^n \mathrm{tr }(d_1(e^i)d_1(e_i))=\sum_{i=0}^n K_\mathfrak{a}(e^i,e_i)=n\]
example
In the case \(\mathfrak{g}=\mathfrak{sl}_2\) and \(\mathfrak{a}=\R^2\ ,\) with the standard representation, one has \[\gamma=d_1(e^1)d_1(e_1)+d_1(e^2)d_1(e_3)+d_1(e^3)d_1(e_3)\ :\] \[=d_1(N)d^{(0)}(M)+d_1(M)d^{(0)}(N)+\frac{1}{2}d_1(H)d_1(H)\ :\] \[=\begin{bmatrix} 0&0\\1&0\end{bmatrix}\begin{bmatrix} 0&1\\0&0\end{bmatrix}+ \begin{bmatrix} 0&1\\0&0\end{bmatrix}\begin{bmatrix} 0&0\\1&0\end{bmatrix}+\frac{1}{2} \begin{bmatrix} 1&0\\0&-1\end{bmatrix}\begin{bmatrix} 1&0\\0&-1\end{bmatrix}\ :\] \[=\frac{3}{2}\begin{bmatrix} 1&0\\0&1\end{bmatrix}\] One checks that indeed \( \mathrm{tr\ }\gamma=3\ .\)
lemma
Suppose \(\dim\mathfrak{a}<\infty\ .\) Then \[\gamma d_1(x)=d_1(x)\gamma\]
proof
\[\gamma d_1(x)-d_1(x)\gamma\ :\] \[=\sum_{i=1}^n d_1(e^i)d_1(e_i)d_1(x)-d_1(x)\sum_{i=1}^n d_1(e^i)d_1(e_i)\ :\] \[=\sum_{i=1}^n d_1(e^i)d_1([e_i,x])+\sum_{i=1}^n d_1(e^i)d_1(x)d_1(e_i)-\sum_{i=1}^n d_1(e^i)d_1(x)d(e_i)+\sum_{i=1}^n d_1([e^i,x])d_1(e_i)\ :\] \[=\sum_{i=1}^n d_1(e^i)d_1([e_i,x])+\sum_{i=1}^n d_1([e^i,x])d_1(e_i)\ :\] \[=-\sum_{i,j=1}^n \tilde{K}_{\mathfrak{a}}(x,[e_i,e^j])d_1(e^i)d_1(e_j)+\sum_{i,j=1}^n \tilde{K}_{\mathfrak{a}}(x,[e_j,e^i]) d_1(e^j) d_1(e_i)\ :\] \[=0\]
corollary
The map \(\gamma\) is a \(\mathfrak{g}\)-endomorphism.
lemma - Fitting decomposition
Let \(\alpha\in \mathrm{End}_\mathfrak{g}(\mathfrak{a})\ ,\) with \(\dim\mathfrak{a}<\infty\ .\)
Then \(\mathfrak{a}=\mathfrak{a}_0\oplus\mathfrak{a}_1\ ,\) where \(\mathfrak{a}_i\) is invariant under \(\alpha\) and \(\mathfrak{g}\ .\)
Moreover, of one denotes the restriction of \(\alpha\) to \(\mathfrak{a}_i\) by \(\alpha_i\ ,\) one has that \(\alpha_0\) is nilpotent and \(\alpha_1\) is invertible.
proof
One has s decreasing sequence of subspaces \[ \mathfrak{a}\supset \alpha\mathfrak{a}\supset \alpha^2 \mathfrak{a}\supset\cdots\] where \(\alpha^m\) denotes the \(m\)th power of \(\alpha\ .\)
Since \(\mathfrak{a}\) is finite-dimensional, this stabilizes, say at \(k\ .\)
Define \(\mathfrak{a}_1=\alpha^k \mathfrak{a}\ .\)
This is \(\alpha\)-invariant by construction, and \(\mathfrak{g}\)-invariant since \(\alpha\) commutes with the \(\mathfrak{g}\)-action on \(\mathfrak{a}\ .\)
Let \(\mathfrak{\beta}_i=\ker \alpha^i\ .\)
Then \[\mathfrak{b}_0\subset\mathfrak{b}_1\subset\cdots\subset\mathfrak{a}\] Again,this stabilizes, say at \(l\ .\) Let \(\mathfrak{a}_0=\mathfrak{b}_l\) and observe that \(\mathfrak{a}_0\) is \(\alpha\)-invariant and \(\mathfrak{g}\)-invariant.
Let \(m=\max(k,l)\ .\)
Then \[ \mathfrak{a}_0=\ker \alpha^m,\quad \mathfrak{a}_1=\mathrm{im}\alpha^m\] Take \(x\in\mathfrak{a}\ .\)
Then \(\alpha^m x=\alpha^{2m} y\) for some \(y\in\mathfrak{a}\ ,\) since \(\alpha^m\mathfrak{a}=\alpha^{2m}\mathfrak{a}\ .\)
Write \(x=(x-\alpha^my)+\alpha^m y\in\ker \alpha^m+\mathrm{im}\alpha^m\ .\)
This implies \[\mathfrak{a}=\mathfrak{a}_0+\mathfrak{a}_1\] Let \(z\in \mathfrak{a}_0\cap\mathfrak{a}_1\ .\)
This implies that \(z=\alpha^m w\) and \(\alpha^m z=0\ .\)
It follows that, since \(\alpha^{2m}w=0\ ,\) \(w\in\mathfrak{a}_0\ .\)
Therefore \(\alpha^mw=0\ ,\) or, in other words, \( z=0\ .\) This shows that \(\mathfrak{a}_0\cap\mathfrak{a}_1=0\) and \[\mathfrak{a}=\mathfrak{a}_0\oplus\mathfrak{a}_1\]
Since \(\mathfrak{a}_1=\alpha^m\mathfrak{a}=\alpha^{m+1}\mathfrak{a}=\alpha\mathfrak{a}_1\ ,\) it follows that \(\alpha_1\) is surjective, and therefore an isomorphism.
Denote the projections of \(\mathfrak{a}\rightarrow\mathfrak{a}_i\) by \(\pi_i^0\) and observe they commute with the \(\mathfrak{g}\)-action.
The decomposition \(\mathfrak{a}=\mathfrak{a}_0\oplus\mathfrak{a}_1\) is called the Fitting decomposition of \(\mathfrak{a}\) with respect to \(\alpha\ .\)
theorem
Let \(d_1\) be a representation.
Suppose there exists a nondegenerate trace form \(\tilde{K}_\mathfrak{a}\ .\)
Let \(\mathfrak{a}_0\oplus\mathfrak{a}_1\) be the Fitting decomposition with respect to \(\gamma\ .\)
Then \(H^m(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\mathfrak{a})=H^m(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\mathfrak{a}_0)\ .\)
remark
Contrary to the usual statement of this theorem, the forms do not need to be antisymmetric.
proof
Consider the Fitting decomposition of \(\mathfrak{a}\) with respect to \(\gamma\ .\) Take \([\zeta_m]\in H^m(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\mathfrak{a})\) and let \[\pi^m\zeta_m=(-1)^{m-1}\gamma^m\omega_m\] Then, since \( \gamma^{m+1}d^m=d^m\gamma^m\) and \( \pi^{m+1}d^m=d^m\pi^m\ ,\) one has \[0=\pi^{m+1}d^m\zeta_m=d^m\pi^m\zeta_m=(-1)^{m-1}d^m \gamma^m\omega_m=(-1)^{m-1}\gamma^{m+1}d^m \omega_m\] Since \(\gamma\) is an isomorphism on \(\mathfrak{a}_1\ ,\) this shows that \(d^m\omega_m=0\ .\)
Then define \[ \mu_{m-1}(x_1,\cdots,x_{m-1})=\sum_{i=1}^n d_1(e^i)\omega_m(x_1,\cdots,x_{m-1},e_i)\] (Here one needs the trace form to be nondegenerate, in order to define the dual basis). Then \[0=\sum_{i=1}^n d_1(e^i)d^m\omega_m(x_1,\dots,x_m,e_i)\ :\] \[=\sum_{i=1}^n (-1)^{m} d_1(e^i)d_1(e_i) \omega_m(x_1,\dots,x_{m})\ :\] \[+\sum_{k=1}^{m}\sum_{i=1}^n(-1)^{k-1} d_1(e^i) d_1(x_k) \omega_m(x_1,\dots,\hat{x}_k,\dots,x_m,e_i)\ :\] \[-\sum_{k=1}^{m}\sum_{i=1}^n (-1)^{k-1} d_1(e^i)\omega_m(x_1,\dots,\hat{x}_k,\dots,[x_k,e_i])\ :\] \[-\sum_{k=1}^{m}\sum_{l=1}^{k-1}\sum_{i=1}^n(-1)^{l-1} d_1(e^i) \omega_m(x_1,\dots,\hat{x}_l,\dots,[x_l,x_k],\dots,e_i)\ :\] \[=(-1)^m\gamma\omega_m(x_1,\dots,x_{m})\ :\] \[+\sum_{k=1}^{m}\sum_{i=1}^n(-1)^{k-1} d_1(x_k) d_1(e^i)\omega_m(x_1,\dots,\hat{x}_k,\dots,x_m,e_i)\ :\] \[-\sum_{k=1}^{m}\sum_{l=1}^{k-1}\sum_{i=1}^n(-1)^{l-1} d_1(e^i) \omega_m(x_1,\dots,\hat{x}_l.\dots,[x_l,x_k],\dots,e_i)\ :\] \[-\sum_{k=1}^{m}\sum_{i=1}^n(-1)^{k-1} d_1([x_k,e^i])\omega_m(x_1,\dots,\hat{x}_k,\dots,e_i)\ :\] \[-\sum_{k=1}^{m}\sum_{i=1}^n (-1)^{k-1} d_1(e^i)\omega_m(x_1,\dots,\hat{x}_k,\dots,[x_k,e_i])\ :\] \[=-\pi^m\zeta_m(x_1^1,\dots,x_{m}^m)+d^{m-1}\mu_{m-1}(x_1,\dots,x_m)\ :\] \[+\sum_{k=1}^{m}\sum_{i=1}^n \sum_{p=1}^n(-1)^{k-1} K_\mathfrak{a}(x_k,[e_p,e^i])d_1(e^p)\omega_m(x_1,\dots,\hat{x}_k,\dots,x_m,e_i)\ :\] \[-\sum_{k=1}^{m}\sum_{i=1}^n \sum_{p=1}^n (-1)^{k-1}K_\mathfrak{a}(x_k,[e_i,e^p]) d_1(e^i)\omega_m(x_1,\dots,\hat{x}_k.\dots,x_m,e_p)\ :\] \[=-\pi^m\zeta_m(x_1^1,\dots,x_{m}^m)+d^{m-1}\mu_{m-1}(x_1,\dots,x_m)\] and the theorem is proved.\(\square\)
theorem
Let \(M=\dim(\mathfrak{a}_0)\ .\) Then \(H^m(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\mathfrak{a}_0)=\bigoplus_{\iota=1}^M H^m(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\mathbb{C})\ .\)
proof
Since \(\gamma_0=\gamma|\mathfrak{a}_0\) is nilpotent, its trace on \(\mathfrak{a}_0\) is zero.
But this implies that the representation vanishes on \(\mathfrak{a}_0\ ,\) since \(\mathrm{tr\ }\gamma_0=n\ ,\) where \( n\) is the number of basis vectors \(e_\iota\) of \(\mathfrak{a}_0\) such that \(d_1(e_\iota)\neq 0\ .\)
Therefore \(H^m(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\mathfrak{a}_0)=\bigoplus_{\iota=1}^M H^m(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\mathbb{C})\ ,\) where the action of \(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}\) on \(\mathbb{C}\) is supposed to be trivial, as usual.
corollary
Let \(d_1\) be a nontrivial representation, such that \(\mathfrak{a}\) is irreducible, that is, it contains no \(\mathfrak{g}\)-invariant subspaces.
Suppose there exists a nondegenerate trace form \(\tilde{K}_\mathfrak{a}\ .\)
Then \(H^m(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\mathfrak{a})=0\ .\)
proof
Since the representation is irreducible, one has either \(\mathfrak{a}=\mathfrak{a}_0\) or \(\mathfrak{a}=\mathfrak{a}_1\ .\)
But in the first case the representation would be trivial, which is excluded.
Therefore one is in the second case and the statement follows.
lemma
If \([\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}]=\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}\) then \(H^1(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\mathbb{C})=0\ .\)
proof
Since the representation is trivial, \( d^1\omega^1=0\) implies \(\omega^1([x,y])=0\) for all \(x,y\in\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}\ .\)
But this implies that \( \omega^1(z)=0\) for all \( z\in\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}\ ,\) since every \(z\) can be written as a finite linear combination of commutators.
It follows that \(\omega^1=0\) and therefore trivial (with the representation zero, the only way a one form can be trivial is by being zero).
corollary
Suppose there exists a nondegenerate trace form \(\tilde{K}_\mathfrak{a}\) and \([\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}]=\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}\ .\)
Let \(M=\dim(\mathfrak{a}_0)\ .\)
Then \(H^1(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\mathfrak{a})=H^1(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\mathfrak{a}_0)=\bigoplus_{\iota=1}^{M} H^1(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\mathbb{C})=0\ .\)
definition -lower central series
Define the lower central series of a Lie algebra by \(\mathfrak{g}^0=\mathfrak{g}\) and \(\mathfrak{g}^{i+1}=[\mathfrak{g},\mathfrak{g}^i]\ .\)
proposition
The \(\mathfrak{g}^i\) are ideals of \(\mathfrak{g}\ .\)
proof
For \( i=0\) this is trivial. Suppose \(\mathfrak{g}^i\) is an ideal. Then \[[\mathfrak{g},\mathfrak{g}^{i+1}]=[\mathfrak{g},[\mathfrak{g},\mathfrak{g}^i]]\subset [\mathfrak{g},\mathfrak{g}^i]=\mathfrak{g}^{i+1}\] The proposition follows by induction.
definition
\(\mathfrak{g}\) is called nilpotent if there is an \(n\in\mathbb{N}\) such that \(\mathfrak{g}^n=0\ .\)
proposition
A nilpotent Lie algebra is solvable, but a solvable Lie algebra need not be nilpotent.
proof
The first part follows from \(\mathfrak{g}^{(i)}\subset \mathfrak{g}^i\ .\) An algebra that is solvable bit not nilpotent is the Lie algebra of upper triangular matrices in \(\mathfrak{gl}_n\ .\)
proposition
If \(\mathfrak{g}\) is nilpotent, then so are all subalgebras and homomorphic images.
proof
Let \( \mathfrak{h}\) be a subalgebra. Then \( \mathfrak{h}^{0}\subset\mathfrak{g}^{0}\ .\) Assume \(\mathfrak{h}^{i}\subset\mathfrak{g}^{i}\ .\) Then \[ \mathfrak{h}^{i+1}=[\mathfrak{g},\mathfrak{h}^{i}]\subset [\mathfrak{g},\mathfrak{g}^{i}]=\mathfrak{g}^{i+1}\] and the statement is proved by induction. Similarly, let \(\phi:\mathfrak{g}\rightarrow \mathfrak{h}\) be surjective, and assume \(\phi:\mathfrak{g}^{i}\rightarrow \mathfrak{h}^{i}\) to be surjective. Then \[\phi(\mathfrak{g}^{i+1})=\phi([\mathfrak{g},\mathfrak{g}^{i}])=[\phi(\mathfrak{g}),\phi(\mathfrak{g}^{i})]= [\mathfrak{h},\mathfrak{h}^{i}]=\mathfrak{h}^{i+1}\]
proposition
Let \(\mathcal{Z}(\mathfrak{g})\) denote the center of \(\mathfrak{g}\ ,\) that is, \[\mathcal{Z}(\mathfrak{g})=\{x\in \mathfrak{g}|[x,y]=0 \quad \forall y\in\mathfrak{g}\}\] If \(\mathfrak{g}/\mathcal{Z}(\mathfrak{g})\) is nilpotent, then \(\mathfrak{g}\) is nilpotent.
proof
Say \(\mathfrak{g}^n\subset \mathcal{Z}(\mathfrak{g})\ ,\) then \(\mathfrak{g}^{n+1}=[\mathfrak{g},\mathfrak{g}^{n}]\subset [\mathfrak{g},\mathcal{Z}(\mathfrak{g})]=0\ .\)
proposition
If \(\mathfrak{g}\) is nilpotent and nonzero, then so is \(\mathcal{Z}(\mathfrak{g})\neq 0\ .\)
proof
Let \( n \) be the minimal order such that \(\mathfrak{g}^n=0\ ,\) then \(\mathfrak{g}^{n-1}\subset \mathcal{Z}(\mathfrak{g})\ .\)
lemma
If \(x\in \mathfrak{gl}(V)\) is nilpotent, then \( \mathrm{ad}(x) \) is nilpotent. In particular, if \(x^n=0\) then \(\mathrm{ad}^{2n}(x)=0\ .\)
proof
Define \(\lambda_x, \rho_x\in\mathrm{End}(\mathrm{End}(V))\) by \[ \lambda_x y=xy,\quad \rho_x y=yx\] These are nilpotent, since for instance, \(\lambda_x^n=\lambda_{x^n}\ .\) If \(x^n=0\ ,\) then \((\lambda_x-\rho_x)^{2n}=0\) (since \(\lambda_x \rho_x=\rho_x\lambda_x\)). This proves the statement, since \(\mathrm{ad}(x)=\lambda_x-\rho_x\ .\)
theorem
Let \(\mathfrak{g}\) be a subalgebra of \(\mathfrak{gl}(V)\ ,\) with \(0<\dim V<\infty\ .\) If \(\mathfrak{g}\) consists of nilpotent endomorphisms, then there exists \(0\neq v\in V\) such that \(d^{(0)}(\mathfrak{g})v=0\ .\)
proof
The proof is by induction on \(\dim\mathfrak{g}\ .\) The statement is obvious if the dimension is zero, since any \(v\in V\) will do.
Suppose \(\mathfrak{h}\) is a subalgebra of \(\mathfrak{g}\ .\)
Then \(\mathfrak{h}\) acts via \(\mathrm{ad}\) as a Lie algebra of nilpotent linear transformations on \(\mathfrak{g}\ ,\) and therefore on \(\mathfrak{g}/\mathfrak{h}\ .\)
Since \(\dim\mathfrak{h}<\dim\mathfrak{g}\) one can use the induction hypothesis to conclude that there exists a vextor \(x+\mathfrak{h}\ ,\) \( x\notin \mathfrak{h}\ ,\) such that \([y,x]=0\) for any \(y\in \mathfrak{h}\ .\)
Thus \(\mathfrak{h}\) is properly contained in its normalizer \[ N_\mathfrak{g}(\mathfrak{h})=\{x\in\mathfrak{g}|[x,\mathfrak{h}]\subset\mathfrak{h}\}\]
The normalizer is a subalgebra, so if one takes \(\mathfrak{h}\) to be a maximal proper subalgebra, then its normalizer must be the whole \(\mathfrak{g}\ ,\) that is to say, \(\mathfrak{h}\) is an ideal in \(\mathfrak{g}\ .\)
Take \(0\neq x\in\mathfrak{g}/\mathfrak{h}\) and let \(\mathfrak{x}\) be the subalgebra generated by \(x\ .\)
Then the inverse image of \(\mathfrak{x}\) in \(\mathfrak{g}\) is a subalgebra properly containing \(\mathfrak{h}\ ,\) that is, it is \(\mathfrak{g}\ .\)
This only makes sense if there is basically one such \(x\ ,\) and it follows that \(\dim\mathfrak{g}/\mathfrak{h}=1\ .\) One writes \[ \mathfrak{g}=\mathfrak{h}+ \mathbb{C} x\ .\] By induction, \(\mathcal{W}=\{v\in V|d^{(0)}(\mathfrak{h})v=0\}\) is nonzero. One has for \(x\in\mathfrak{g}\ ,\) \(y\in\mathfrak{h}\) and \( w\in\mathcal{W}\) that \[d_1(y)d_1(x)w=d_1(x)d_1(y)w-d_1([x,y])w=0\ .\] This implies that \(d_1(x)w\in \mathcal{W}\ ,\) that is, \(\mathcal{W}\) is invariant under \(\mathfrak{g}\ .\) Take \(x\in\mathfrak{x}\) as before.
Then (since \(\dim\mathfrak{x}=1\)) there exists a nonzero \( v\in\mathcal{W}\) such that \(d_1(x)v=0\ .\) This implies that \(d_1(\mathfrak{g})v=0\ ,\) as desired.
theorem (Engel)
If all all elements of \(\mathfrak{g}\) are ad-nilpotent, then \(\mathfrak{g}\) is nilpotent.
proof
Identifying \(\mathrm{ad\ }(x)\) with a nilpotent element in \(\mathrm{End}(\mathfrak{g})\ ,\) one conludes to the existence of an \(x\in\mathfrak{g}\) such that \(\mathrm{ad\ }(\mathfrak{g})x=0\ ,\) that, \(x\in \mathcal{Z}(\mathfrak{g})\neq 0\ .\)
Then \(\mathfrak{g}/\mathcal{Z}(\mathfrak{g})\) again consists of ad-nilpotent elements and \(\dim \mathfrak{g}/\mathcal{Z}(\mathfrak{g})< \dim \mathfrak{g}\ .\)
Using induction on the dimension, one concludes that \(\mathfrak{g}/\mathcal{Z}(\mathfrak{g})\) is nilpotent.
It follows that \(\mathfrak{g}\) is nilpotent.
corollary
If \(\mathfrak{g}\) is solvable, then \([\mathfrak{g},\mathfrak{g}]\) is nilpotent.
lemma
Let \(\mathfrak{g}\) be nilpotent and \(\mathfrak{h}\) a nonzero ideal of \(\mathfrak{g}\ .\) Then \(\mathfrak{h}\cap\mathcal{Z}(\mathfrak{g})\neq 0\) (and in particular, \(\mathcal{Z}(\mathfrak{g})\neq 0\)).
proof
If \(\mathfrak{g}^n=0\) then \( (\mathrm{ad\ }(x))^n=0\ .\) Consider \( \mathfrak{h}\) as the representation space (with \(d^{(0)}=\mathrm{ad}\)). Then there exist an element \(h\in\mathfrak{h}\) such that \[ ad(\mathfrak{g})h=0\ .\] This is equivalent with saying that \(h\in\mathfrak{h}\cap\mathcal{Z}(\mathfrak{g})\neq 0\ .\)
the field
As remarked in the beginning of this lecture, at this point we need our field to have characteristic zero and we also assume it to be closed.
definition + remarks
One calls \(x\in\mathrm{End}(\mathfrak{a})\) semisimple if the roots of its minimal polynomial over \(\mathbb{C}\) are all distinct.
This is equivalent to saying that \( x\) is diagonizable, since one can take its eigenvectors as a basis of \(\mathfrak{a}\ .\)
(In we work in a general field, one requires here that the roots of the minimal polynomial are contained in the field; such a field is called a splitting field relative to \(x\ .\))
If two endomorphisms commute, they can be simultaneously diagonalized.
A semisimple endomorphism remains semisimple when restricted to an invariant subspace.
proposition
Let \(\mathfrak{a}\) be a finite dimensional vectorspace over \(\mathbb{C}\ ,\) \(x\in\mathrm{End}(\mathfrak{a})\ .\)
There exist unique \(x_s, x_n\in\mathrm{End}(\mathfrak{a})\) such that \(x=x_s+x_n\ ,\) \(x_s\) is semisimple, \(x_n\) is nilpotent and \(x_s\) and \(x_n\) commute.
proof
Let \( \lambda_1,\cdots,\lambda_k\) be the distinct eigenvalues of \(x\) with multiplicities \(m_1,\cdots,m_k\ .\) Its characteristic polynomial is then \(\chi(\lambda)=\prod_{i=1}^k (\lambda-\lambda_i)^{m_i}\ .\) Let \( V_i=\mathrm{ker} (x-\lambda_i)^{m_i}\ ,\) then \(V=\bigoplus_{i=1}^k V_i\ .\)
Using the Chinese Remainder Theorem we find a polynomial \(p(\lambda)\) such that \(p(\lambda)=\lambda_i \mathrm{\ mod\ } (\lambda-\lambda_i)^{m_i}\) and \(p(\lambda)=0 \mathrm{\ mod\ } \lambda\ .\)
Let \(q(\lambda)=\lambda-p(\lambda)\ .\)
Then put \(x_s=p(x)\) and \(x_n=q(x)\ .\) Since both are polynomial in \(x\ ,\) they commute.
One has \(x_s-\lambda_i |V_i=0\ ,\) that is, \(x_s\)acts diagonally on \(V\ ,\) since on each \(V_i\) the characteristic polynomial is \((\lambda-\lambda_i)^{m_i}\ .\)
Furthermore \(x_n=x-x_s\) is nilpotent, since on each \(V_i\) it obeys its own characteristic equation \( x_n^{m_i}=0\ ,\) so with \(m=\mathrm{max}_{i=1,\ldots,k}m_i\) one has \(x_n^m=0\ .\)
Any other such decomposition \(x=s+n\) would lead to \(x_s-s=n-x_n\ .\) Since \(s\) and \(n\) commute, they also commute with \(x\) and therefore with \(x_s\) and \(x_n\ .\)
Since the sum of commuting semisimple operators is semisimple and the sum of nilpotent operators nilpotent, and the only operator that is both semisimple and nilpotent is \(0\ ,\) one must conclude that \(s=x_s\) and \(n=x_n\ .\)
lemma
\(\mathrm{Der}(\mathfrak{g})\) contains the semisimple and nilpotent parts in \(\mathrm{End}(\mathfrak{g})\) of its elements.
proof
If \(\delta\in \mathrm{Der}(\mathfrak{g})\ ,\) let \(\delta_s, \delta_n\in \mathrm{End}(\mathfrak{g})\) be its semisimple and nilpotent part, respectively. We show that \(\delta_s\in \mathrm{Der}(\mathfrak{g})\ .\)
For \(\lambda\in\mathbb{C}\ ,\) let \(\mathfrak{g}_\lambda=\left\{x\in\mathfrak{g}|(\delta-\lambda)^k x=0\mathrm{\ for\ some\ } k \right\}\ .\) Then \(\delta_s\) acts on \(\mathfrak{g}_\lambda\) by multiplication by \(\lambda\ .\)
One verifies that \([\mathfrak{g}_\lambda,\mathfrak{g}_\mu]\subset\mathfrak{g}_{\lambda+\mu}\ :\)
One has \((\delta-(\lambda+\mu))^n[x,y]=\sum_{i=0}^n\binom{n}{i}[(\delta-\lambda)^{n-i} x,(\delta-\mu)^i y]\ .\)
Indeed, for \(n=1\) this reads \((\delta-(\lambda+\mu))[x,y]=[\delta x,y]+[x,\delta y]-(\lambda+\mu)[x,y]=[(\delta-\lambda) x,y]+[x,(\delta-\mu) y]\) and the general inductive step is now standard.
Thus one has \(\delta_s[x,y]=[\delta_s x,y]+[x,\delta_s y]\) for \(x\in\mathfrak{g}_\lambda, y\in \mathfrak{g}_\mu\ .\)
Since \(\mathfrak{g}=\bigoplus_\lambda \mathfrak{g}_\lambda\ ,\) it follows that \(\delta_s\) is a derivation.
definition
Define a representation of \(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}\) on \(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}'=C^1(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\mathbb{C})\) as follows: \[(b_1(x)c_1)(y)=-c_1([x,y])\]
well defined
\[ (b_1([x,y])c_1)(z)=-c_1([[x,y],z])\ :\] \[=-c_1([x,[y,z]])+c_1([y,[x,z]])\ :\] \[=(b_1(x)c_1)([y,z])-(b_1(y)c_1)([x,z])\ :\] \[= -(b_1(y)b_1(x)c_1)(z)+(b_1(x)b_1(y)c_1)(z)\ :\] \[=([b_1(x),b_1(y)]c_1)(z)\]
lemma
Let \(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}\) be a Lie algebra. Suppose there exists a nondegenerate trace form \(K_{\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}'}\ .\) If \([\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}]=\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}\) then \(H^2(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\mathbb{C})=0\ .\)
remark
The following proofs rely on the fact that \(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}\) is semisimple.
This is proved in the literature, but not yet in these notes.
Alternatively, one could require that \(H^1(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\cdot)=0\ .\)
proof
Let for \(m\geq 1\) a map \(\phi^m:C^m(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\mathbb{C})\rightarrow C^{m-1}(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}')\) be given by \[ (\phi^m u_m)(x_1,\dots,x_{m-1})(x)=u_m(x_1,\dots,x_{m-1},x)\] Since \[ [(b^{m-1}\phi^m u_m)(x_1,\dots,x_m)](x)=\ :\] \[=\sum_{i=1}^m (-1)^{i-1} b_1(x_i) \phi^m u_m (x_1,\dots,\hat{x}_i,\dots,x_m)(x)-\sum_{i<j}(-1)^{i-1} \phi^m u_m (x_1,\dots,\hat{x}_i,\dots,[x_i,x_j]\dots,x_m)(x)\ :\] \[ =-\sum_{i=1}^m (-1)^{i-1} u_m (x_1,\dots,\hat{x}_i,\dots,x_m,[x_i,x])-\sum_{i<j}(-1)^{i-1} u_m (x_1,\dots,\hat{x}_i,\dots,[x_i,x_j]\dots,x_m,x)\ :\] \[ = - d^m u_m (x_1,\dots,x_m,x)\ :\] \[ =- [\phi^{m+1} d^m u_m (x_1,\dots,x_m)](x)\] This implies that \(b^{m-1}\phi^m=-\phi^{m+1} d^m\) and in particular that \(\phi^m:Z^m(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\mathbb{C})\rightarrow Z^{m-1}(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}')\ .\)
Take \(\omega_2\in Z^2(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\mathbb{C})\ .\) Then \(b^1 \phi^2\omega_2 =0\ .\)
It follows from the assumptions that \(H^1( \tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}')=0\ .\)
This implies that there exists a \( \beta_1\in C^{0}(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}')=\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}'\) such that \(\phi\omega_2=b\beta_1\) and \[\omega_2(x,y)= \phi^2\omega_2(x)(y)=b\beta_1(x)(y)=b_1(x)\beta_1(y)=-\beta_1([x,y])=d^1\beta_1(x,y)\] This proves that \(\omega_2=d^1\beta_1\ .\)
remark
These cohomology results were obtained by Whitehead in the antisymmetric case.
There is not an analogous result for \(H_{\wedge}^3(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\mathbb{C})\ .\)
This is related to the fact that \([d^2 K_{\mathfrak{g}'}]\in H_{\wedge}^3(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\mathbb{C})\ .\)
theorem (Weyl)
Suppose \(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}\) and \(\mathfrak{a}\) are finite dimensional. If \([\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}]=\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}\) then \(\mathfrak{a}\) is completely reducible, that is, if \(\mathfrak{b}\) is a \(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}\)-invariant subspace of \(\mathfrak{a}\ ,\) then there exists a \(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}\)-invariant direct summand to \(\mathfrak{b}\ .\)
proof
Let \(\mathfrak{b}\) be a \(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}\)-invariant subspace of \(\mathfrak{a}\ .\) The idea of the proof is as follows.
Let \(P_\mathfrak{b}\) be the projector on \(\mathfrak{b}\ .\) If \(P_\mathfrak{b}\) commutes with the \(\mathfrak{g}\)-action, we are done, since then we find a direct summand by letting \(1-P_\mathfrak{b}\) act on \(\mathfrak{a}\ .\)
To make \(P_\mathfrak{b}\) commute with the action, one perturbs it with another map \(c^0\ .\)
In order for \(P_\mathfrak{b}+c^0\) to be a projection on \(\mathfrak{b}\) one needs that \(\mathrm{im\ }c^0 \subset \mathfrak{b}\) and \(\mathfrak{b}\subset \ker c^0\) (since \(P_\mathfrak{b}\) is the identity on \(\mathfrak{b}\)).
These considerations lead to the following definition. Define \(\mathcal{W}\) to be the space of all \(A\in\mathrm{End}(\mathfrak{a})\) such that \[ \mathrm{im\ }A\subset \mathfrak{b}\subset \ker A\ .\] Then \(\mathcal{W}\) is a subspace: Let \(a\in \mathfrak{a}, b\in\mathfrak{b}\) and \(A,B \in \mathcal{W}\ .\) Then \((A+B)b = Ab +Bb=0\) and \( (A+B)a=Aa+Ab \in \mathfrak{b}\ .\)
Define a representation \(\delta_1\) of \(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}\) on \(\mathcal{W}\) by \[ \delta_1(x)A=[d_1,A]_{\mathrm{End}(\mathfrak{a})}\] Let \(P_\mathfrak{b}\) be a projector on \(\mathfrak{b}\) as a vectorspace. Then \([d_1(x),P_\mathfrak{b}]_{\mathrm{End}(\mathfrak{a}}\in \mathcal{W}\ .\) Therefore \( c^1\ ,\) defined by \[ c^1(x)=[d_1(x),P_\mathfrak{b}]_{\mathrm{End}(\mathfrak{a})}\] is a linear map from \(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}\) to \(\mathcal{W}\ ,\) that is, \(c^1\in C^1(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\mathcal{W})\ .\)
Observe that one cannot say\[c^1=\delta P_\mathfrak{b}\] for the simple reason that \(P_\mathfrak{b}\notin\mathcal{W}\ .\) Then \[ \delta^1 c^1(x,y)=\delta_1(x)c^1(y)-\delta_1(y)c^1(x)-c^1([x,y])\ :\] \[=\delta_1(x)[d^{(0)}(y),P_\mathfrak{b}]_{\mathrm{End}(\mathfrak{a})}-\delta^{(0)}(y)[d_1(x),P_\mathfrak{b}]_{\mathrm{End}(\mathfrak{a})} -[d_1([x,y]),P_\mathfrak{b}]_{\mathrm{End}(\mathfrak{a})}\ :\] \[=[d_1(x),[d_1(y),P_\mathfrak{b}]_{\mathrm{End}(\mathfrak{a})}]_{\mathrm{End}(\mathfrak{a})} -[d_1(y),[d_1(x),P_\mathfrak{b}]_{\mathrm{End}(\mathfrak{a})}]_{\mathrm{End}(\mathfrak{a})} -[d_1([x,y]),P_\mathfrak{b}]_{\mathrm{End}(\mathfrak{a})}\ :\] \[=[[d_1(x),d_1(y)]_{\mathrm{End}(\mathfrak{a})},P_\mathfrak{b}]_{\mathrm{End}(\mathfrak{a})} -[d_1([x,y]),P_\mathfrak{b}]_{\mathrm{End}(\mathfrak{a})}\ :\] \[=0\] Since \(H^1(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\mathcal{W})=0\ ,\) one has \(c^1=\delta c^0\ .\) Then, with \(\mathcal{P}_\mathfrak{b}=P_\mathfrak{b}-c^0\ ,\) \[[d_1(x),\mathcal{P}_\mathfrak{b}]=c^1(x)-\delta_1(x)c^0=c^1(x)-\delta c^0(x)=0\] One has \( \mathcal{P}_\mathfrak{b}a\in \mathfrak{b}\) for \(a\in\mathfrak{a}\) and \(\mathcal{P}_\mathfrak{b}b=P_\mathfrak{b}b=b\) for \(b\in\mathfrak{b}\ .\)
The conclusion is that \( \mathcal{P}_\mathfrak{b}\) is a projector on \(\mathfrak{b}\) as a \(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}\)-module (and therefore \((1-\mathcal{P}_\mathfrak{b}) \) is a projector on the complementary subspace).
Since \(\mathfrak{a}\) is finite-dimensional, the result can be proved using induction.
theorem
Suppose \(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}\) and \(\mathfrak{a}\) are finite dimensional.
Suppose there exists a nondegenerate trace form \(K_{\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}'}\ .\)
If \([\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}]=\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}\) then any extension of \(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}}\) by \(\mathfrak{a}\) is trivial.
proof
This follows from the fact that \(H^2(\tilde{\mathfrak{g}},\mathfrak{a})=0\ .\)
references
- Humphreys, James E. Introduction to Lie algebras and representation theory. Graduate Texts in Mathematics, Vol. 9. Springer-Verlag, New York-Berlin, 1972. xii+169 pp.